Not So Mere Natural Law

Monday, 02-03-2014

People who think about natural law consider it in various ways.

Moral philosophers are interested in what it is -- political philosophers, in what light it might shed on law and government -- casuists, in how it might help them clear up difficult moral problems -- epistemologists, in how we know it -- historians, in how belief in it has moved individuals and nations -- moral apologists, in how the universal dim awareness of it can be cleansed, enlarged, and deepened -- psychologists, in how the attempt to deny it distorts personality -- metaphysicians, in what the structure of reality must be like for there to be such a thing in the first place -- theologians, in how its reality points to the reality of God.

If we suppose that each of these groups pays close attention to what the others are doing, we will be disappointed.  To a surprising degree, each group minds its own business, blithely assuming that its business and the others’ businesses are independent.  “To understand this, we don’t need to understand that too.”  Unfortunately, this assumption is wrong.

A historian, for instance, may think that he doesn’t need to know much about the thing believed in order to understand how believing in it has influenced people.  To understand how belief in natural law has moved nations, he may not even need to know whether it is real.  But this is not so.

Why not?  Consider how believing that natural law is real is different than believing, say, that the planet Jupiter is composed mostly of hydrogen.  We have no inside knowledge, no inner awareness, of the composition of Jupiter.  But through conscience, we do have a certain inside knowledge of natural law; the rational mind “participates” in its reality.  So to affirm or deny that Jupiter is mostly hydrogen is to affirm or deny something outside myself, but to affirm or deny conscience is to affirm or deny myself.  Wouldn’t a good historian see that this must make a difference to how people think and behave?

“To understand this, we don’t need to understand that too.”  Some moral thinkers make the same assumption, and I am more and more convinced that for them it is an even greater folly.  Despite his greatness, C.S. Lewis makes this mistake in his great work The Abolition of Man.  Just as an earlier book was about “mere” Christianity, so one might say this superb essay is about “mere” natural law, and it is much the same sort of splendid failure.  I do not bandy these adjectives lightly.  Though hardly noticed by most specialists, The Abolition of Man is one of the twentieth century’s most luminous brief works about natural law.   Now that the spirit of Nimrod has reawakened, and the voice of the transhumanist is heard in the land, it has more to teach than ever.  Yet just as in the former book, so in this one, the mere just doesn’t work.

Lewis was so intent to avoid the baggage of Western metaphysics that he would not even use the traditional term “natural law”; instead, seeking a term without associations, he called it the “Tao.”  Yet this merely entangled him in the unintended associations of Eastern metaphysics.  So determined was he not to discuss the great question of whether natural law presupposes God, he ended up giving the unintended impression that it doesn’t.

If the book succeeds in other ways – if it accurately diagnoses subjectivism about values, if it successfully show how every attempt to deny the natural law depends on such shreds of natural law as it retains, if it correctly forecasts what refashioning human nature would really mean -- it does so despite its failed minimalism, not because of it.

For a more recent example of failed minimalism in natural law, consider the so-called New Natural Law theory, or NNL.

According to the classical Western natural law tradition, human nature is richly endowed with inclinations which point toward God.  Even without knowing Him as He knows Himself, even without the unaided natural power to attain Him, even without understanding what it actually is that we long for, in fact we long for Him.  We long for Him not only as something good, but as our supreme good, more than we love our very selves.   This longing for God is not only supernatural but natural, and it is linked with other Godward leanings.  We are naturally inclined to worship, naturallyinclined even to offer sacrifice.  The thwarting or misdirection of such inclinations, under the influence of sin, has grave consequences, far greater than what Freud thought happens when libido is repressed.  Understanding them, then, is a matter of the first importance.

But the NNL rejects all of this.  Rather than supposing that we are naturally and spontaneously drawn to God, it views us as drawn to “religion.”  Rather than supposing that religion lies in the loving service of God, it views it as lying in a relationship with some source of meaning which we conceive as greater than ourselves.  And rather than supposing that this relationship is our supreme good, it views it as merely one “basic” good among others -- no more important than, say, the good of play.

One is reminded of a remark by a certain member of Alcoholics Anonymous, when asked by an interviewer what he took the second of the famous Twelve Steps to mean.  The second step declares. “We came to believe that a Power greater than ourselves could restore us to sanity.”

“For me,” he said, “it’s electricity.”

Next:  Beyond the border of mere

What saves Mere Christianity

Tuesday, 01-28-2014

The previous post concluded by finding that if “mere” Christianity means merely what all or almost all who call themselves Christians have believed, there is nothing left of it.  Lewis’s book would seem to be demolished.  But it isn’t.  It is a great book.

What saves the book is that although Lewis says he is defending what all or almost all who have called themselves Christians have believed, he isn’t really; he only thinks he is.  He is actually defending a particular conception of what is truly most central to the Church founded by Christ.  A very particular conception.

In fact, it is a high-church Anglican conception, of roughly the sort held by John Henry Newman before he became Catholic.  This type is rare among actual Anglicans, perhaps because so many of those who hold it end up joining Newman on the other side of the Tiber.  It looks remarkably like Catholicism with a few pieces missing -- just enough of them to allow putting off the decision to convert.  As Newman discovered, the difficulty is that these missing pieces want to be replaced; the holes cry out to them, “Return!”

For example, although Lewis stops short of a full-blown Catholic account of the sacraments, he clearly defends the Catholic view that they are more than mere symbols; they are symbols plus, symbols through which God is actually bringing about the thing symbolized.  Baptism is not just a symbol of new birth but a new birth, marriage is not just a symbol of joining but a joining, and so on.

Whatever Lewis thought it was, this view is far from mere.  Granted, one can hold it without being Catholic, but it is far more characteristic of Catholicism than of Protestantism.  It is especially alien to Evangelical Protestantism, which is curious, because Evangelicals are probably the book’s most enthusiastic readers.  If you wanted to draw Evangelicals to the Catholic Church, you could hardly do better than to have them read Mere Christianity, then point out how Catholic many of their favorite passages are.

But I wish to propose a larger point, which is not about Lewis’s book, and not about Protestantism and Catholicism, but about minimalism.

It is simply this:  Every minimalism is some minimalism.

Lewis’s minimalism turns out to be almost Catholic, but if it hadn’t been almost Catholic, it would have been almost something else.  The mere fact that one avoids certain questions does not make one neutral about their answers. 

Lewis closes his preface with the hope that no reader will take what he calls mere Christianity to be a kind of Christianity, as though someone could be a mere Christian rather than, say, Congregationalist or Greek Orthodox.  He says it is “more like a hall out of which doors open into several rooms,” emphasizing that “the hall is a place to wait in, a place from which to try the various doors, not a place to live in.”  For living in, he thinks, even the worst of the rooms would be preferable to the hall.

But if the hall is defined, not by what is truly most central to the Church founded by Christ, but only by what all or almost all who call themselves Christians have believed, then if the hall exists at all, it is tiny, and some of these doors may not open into rooms at all, but into the street.

Must we then oppose every sort of minimalism?  No.  Every conversation must begin somewhere.  Since one cannot talk about everything at once, one must begin with something that one’s conversational partner is willing to concede.

But this can never last for long.  The mind, like the stomach, desires a meal. Just as some foods are digestible and delicious only in combination with other foods, so also some beliefs are helpful and plausible only in combination with other ideas. In order to stand firm they must have context, as the single stone requires the arch.

Next:  Not so mere natural law

Not so mere Christianity

Saturday, 01-25-2014

One of the twentieth century’s greatest defenses of the Christian faith is C.S. Lewis’s Mere Christianity.  The book contains many good and persuasive arguments; I often recommend it, and expect to go on doing so.  And yet the book’s greatest strength, viewed in one way – the minimalism expressed by the adjective mere -- turns out to be identical with its greatest weakness, viewed in another way.

The point of the mere is that Lewis was not trying to defend a particular conception of Christianity, be it Catholic, Evangelical, Presbyterian, or what have you, but just Christianity.  His strategy was to get the reader into the entrance hall; the reader could decide on his own what room to enter from there.

How wonderful to avoid the sectarian quarrels and go straight to the heart of things.  So what is the problem?  The problem is that Lewis was not really doing that.

In fact, he couldn’t have done that, for consider what kind of mere his mere is.  To go to the heart of things, Lewis would have had to identify and defend the beliefs most truly central to the Church founded by Christ.  But to do that would have risked the very quarrels he was trying to avoid, for as he points out, which beliefs are central is one of the things which the different conceptions of Christianity disagree about.  Instead, Lewis said, his aim was to defend only the beliefs about God and man shared by almost all or almost all who have called themselves Christians.

To put it another way, his mere is not the essential mere, but only the statistical mere.

But aren’t these two meres the same thing?  Aren’t the beliefs most truly central to the Church founded by Christ the very same as the beliefs of most people who call themselves Christians?  Hasn’t orthodox Christian faith been defined by St. Vincent of Lerins as “what has been believed everywhere, always, and by all”?

St. Vincent did say that.  But his excellent criterion has no meaning unless we specify who is meant by that “all.”  Who did St. Vincent himself mean by it?  He meant all who cling to the Sacred Tradition of the Catholic Church.  As he explained, “We shall hold to this rule if we follow universality, antiquity, and consent. We shall follow universality if we acknowledge that one Faith to be true which the whole Church throughout the world confesses; antiquity if we in no wise depart from those interpretations which it is clear that our ancestors and fathers proclaimed; consent, if in antiquity itself, we keep following the definitions and opinions of all, or certainly nearly all, Bishops and Doctors alike.”

Unlike St. Vincent’s “all,” which is really a criterion of adherence to Sacred Tradition, Lewis’s statistical “all” opens the door to a zoological garden of beliefs, and every day the zoo grows larger.  Mary Baker Eddy called herself a Christian.  The “God is dead” theologians of the nineteen-sixties called themselves Christians.  Mormons, who think God one of an infinity of gods, call themselves Christians (at least these days they do).  I used to know an Episcopalian chaplain who denied the Resurrection, but recited the Creed “as an act of solidarity with the community."

Some of these species of belief are pretty well populated, so that if mere Christianity means merely what all or almost all who call themselves Christians have believed, there is nothing left of it.

But I suggested that the book is great.  So what saves it?  See the next post for the answer.

Is love selfish?

Monday, 01-20-2014

The other day, one of my students suggested that there is no such thing a morality, because to be moral is to be unselfish, and even so-called moral behavior is really selfish at the core.  His example was that even a martyr isn’t acting morally, because he gains something by dying for others.

It would be easy to expand the list of examples.  Friendship is selfish because we get something from it; a mother’s care for her child is selfish because it makes her happy.

This view is mistaken, but there are kernels of truth in every believable mistake.  Otherwise they couldn’t be believable.  In this case, one of the kernels of truth is that we necessarily seek our own happiness.  The other is that morality has something to do with love, and love is a commitment of the will to the true good of other persons.

The misstep lies in thinking that unselfishness means loving the others instead of myself.  No, I must love them asmyself.  For human beings, the good is of such a nature that unless we share it, we cannot enjoy it at all.

To put it another way, if you think the difference between a selfish and unselfish person is that one sort seeks his own happiness and the other sort doesn’t, then of course you will think there is no such thing as morality, because everyone seeks his own happiness.  The real difference between selfish and unselfish persons lies elsewhere -- in how they are related to other selves.

The selfish person is indifferent to them.  He thinks not caring about other selves will make him happy.  This is a delusion, which makes him miserable.

But the unselfish person identifies with other selves.  If those he loves flourish, he flourishes; if not, then not; and so he flourishes.  The greatest love is to lay down his life for them – not because he is indifferent to his happiness, but because it is inseparable from theirs.

From this point of view, one might almost say that the problem with the selfish person is not that he desires happiness too much, but that he doesn’t desire it enough.  If only he conceived happiness more adequately, he would not seek it in such a cramped and unimaginative way.  Only the one who spends himself saves himself.  Misers lose everything.

The collapse of the universities

Thursday, 01-16-2014

I closed the last post with a question:  Having abandoned the vision on which the medieval university was built, what are modern universities organized around?  The answer is “Nothing in particular.”

They are queasy alliances of interest groups which have no ultimate commitments in common.

Among the more respectable things the university tries to be are a job training center, a place for technological research, and an accreditor of fitness for employment.  But universities don’t do any of these things well, and each of them can be better and more cheaply by other kinds of institution.

You don’t need to go to college to learn how to manage a hotel, or to prove that you can program a computer.  Government and industry can carry out technological research just as well at their own facilities.  And college prepares people for employment so poorly that some corporations are now forced to run their own classes in math and English composition.

The university also tries to be a place for doing things that just don’t need to be done at all, like giving young people a place to “discover themselves.”

This which means giving them a place for a protracted period of dissipation while avoiding adult responsibilities.  Parents who think this is the best way for their children to grow up could save money by just sending them on cruises.

Universities offer places for preserving failed ideologies and validating faddish “identities,” but we have politics for that; we don’t need universities.

And they are massive public-works programs for keeping a larger number of people employed as scholars than could otherwise find that kind of work.  We do need scholars, but let us be honest: Most scholars would be better employed at something else.

The things universities do which other institutions can do better eventually will be done by other institutions.  The things they do which don’t need to be done will eventually lose public support.  I will not mourn these changes.  They are overdue.

I will mourn the loss of the one thing universities can do well, which was done in medieval universities, but which the modern university no longer believes in:  Pursuing the vision of the coherence of reality and its friendliness to the mind, and forming minds which are capable of sharing it.

We will have to find another way to do that.  I don’t know what it will be.  I believe it will be found, but it will not be found in my time.  There are signs on the horizon, but they are faint.

And so to reply to Vedder and Denhart:  Gentlemen, you are mistaken.  These are the reasons why the college bubble will pop; this is why the higher education system will collapse.  Not because it is “still tied to its medieval origins.”

 

What’s wrong with universities?

Monday, 01-13-2014

A recent Wall Street Journal article by Richard Vedder and Christopher Denhart concludes, “Many poorly endowed and undistinguished schools may bite the dust, but America flourished when buggy manufacturers went bankrupt thanks to the automobile.  The cleansing would be good for a higher education system still tied to its medieval origins – and for the students it’s robbing.”

Vedder and Denhart are right about the need for reform, but they are mistaken about what kind of reform is needed.  And they are utterly confused in thinking that the problem is that universities are “still tied to medieval origins.”

Medieval students had to master seven elementary studies before going on to advanced degrees.  The first three, called the trivium, were grammar, or the laws of language; rhetoric, or the laws of argument; and dialectic, or the laws of clear thought.  The next four, called the quadrivium, were arithmetic, or the laws of number; geometry, or the laws of figure; music, or the laws of harmony; and astronomy, or the laws of inherent motion.

Why these seven?  Because medieval universities were organized around the view that the universe makes sense, that knowledge is grasping that sense, that the mind can really grasp it, that all knowledge is related, and that all of its parts form a meaningful whole. 

By contrast, our universities are organized around – what?  Actually, they aren’t universities at all, because they have given up their vision, the coherence of universal reality and its friendliness to the rational mind.

Most humanities scholars gave up that view some time ago.  In fact, they mock it.  That’s why we have so little that even pretends to be a core curriculum, and why even general education courses are a smorgasbord.  The pretentious postmodernist credo is “suspicion of metanarratives,” which means no one gets the Big Story right.

Of course that is a Big Story too.  “Once upon a time people believed there was a Big Story which would make sense of things if only they could get it right.  Now we know better, because there isn't any Big Story, so no one gets it right.  And we are the clever ones the ones who got that right.”

How clever are these clever ones?  You tell me.  Several years ago my own university sponsored a freshman assembly about choosing a major.  Faculty in the humanities and sciences presented pep talks for their fields of study; student leaders asked them questions.  The tone of the event was epitomized by the question, “If you were a bar of soap, whose shower would you want to be in?”  Grinningly, the faculty moderator pressed the faculty panelists to answer.

I am ashamed to say that they did.

This is not the sort of problem which can be solved by cost-savings, team-teaching, or distance learning.  Such solutions are merely economic.  The problem is spiritual.

Though scientists have held out longer, belief in the coherence of universal reality is vanishing among them too.  The physicist Werner Heisenberg wrote in his book Across the Frontiers that “Not only is the Universe stranger than we think, it is stranger than we can think.”

This view isn’t a finding of science.  It’s merely a culmination of a line of thought which began with philosophers like Kant, who thought our minds can never really get at reality itself, but only at their own thoughts about reality.

Having abandoned the vision of universal truth on which the medieval university was built, what are modern universities organized around?  Stay tuned.

* “How the College Bubble will Pop,” Wall Street Journal, p. A13, 9 January 2014.

The rest of the witnesses

Monday, 01-06-2014

Last week I was telling the Original Visitor about –

The Original Visitor breaks in:  You don’t have to be so didactic.

Budziszewski:  Why do you care?  You’re a figment of my imagination.

But you’re imagining me to be something like a real reader, and a real reader would find your language patronizing.  “I was telling him,” indeed.

Sorry, that's not my intention.  How would you say it?

I thought we were having a little chat.

All right.  Last week the Original Visitor and I were chatting about the four witnesses.  Better?

Yes, much.

May we now resume our broadcast?

Yes.  You were going to tell me what the third witness is.

Well, you remember that we were talking about our natural design.

Of course.

The second witness was recognition that in fact, we do have a natural design --

I remember.  So?

So the third witness is just recognition of its details.

What do you mean?

If the human person really is a meaningful whole, then each of our various powers and features has moral significance.

For example?

For example, the respiratory power is for breathing, not sniffing airplane glue.

So by meanings and purposes you just mean the functions of our bodily organs.

No, I’m talking about all of our powers and features.  The power of anger is for arousing us to the ordinate defense of endangered goods.  The sexual power is for turning the wheel of the generations uniting the procreative partners.  The power of practical reason is for deliberating well.  The power of wonder is for stirring us up to seek truth, especially the truth about God.  Each of these powers should be used according to its purpose.

A little propaganda, eh, Mr. Blogger?  I see how you slipped in the item about sex.   

I didn’t “slip it in.”  We recognize the inbuilt meaning and purpose of the sexual powers in exactly the same way that we recognize the inbuilt meaning and purpose of, say –

Try anger.  There’s a power for you.  Tell me the “inbuilt meaning and purpose” of the power to become angry, if you can.

Wouldn’t you say that the inbuilt meaning and purpose of anger is to arouse us to the ordinate defense of endangered goods?

Why should that be the purpose?

Be serious.  Apart from arousing us to the ordinate defense of endangered goods, why should there even be such a thing as anger?

And I suppose you’d say, “Apart from the need for posterity, why should there even be such a thing as sex?”

Would I be wrong?

Why not say that the meaning and purpose of sex is simply pleasure?

Because the exercise of every voluntary power is pleasurable, and that tells us nothing about its purpose.  You wouldn’t say that the inbuilt meaning and purpose of the power to eat is simply pleasure, would you?

You said that each of our “powers and features” has moral significance, but all of your examples are what you call “powers.”  Give me an example of a “feature.”

Sure:  The fact that men and women are complementary.

Complementary, like different?

Complementary, like different in a way that makes them correspond, that makes them form a whole.  There is something missing in a man which is more fully present in the woman, and something missing in a woman which is more fully present in the man.  They balance each other.

And why do you say that this fact about us has “moral significance”?

Because any way of life which denies or defies it is asking for trouble.

Every few sentences I want to hit you.

Why?  I don’t have any urge to hit you.

Never mind.  Tell me the fourth witness.

When I do you may hit me anyway.

Why?

Because the fourth witness is all about asking for trouble.

So what is it?

The natural consequences of our deeds.

Hmm.  What do you mean by “natural consequences”?

All of the things that happen to us when -- and because -- our lives cut across the grain of our design.

Like what?

If I cut myself, then I bleed.  If I use a lot of dope, then I become its slave.

So by “natural” consequences you mean bodily consequences.

No, I mean all of the consequences which arise in the course of nature.  If I live by knives, then I die by knives.  If I desert the mother, then my child grows up without a father.  If I hop from bed to bed, then eventually I lose the capacity for intimacy.  If I betray my friends, then eventually I have no friends.

Okay, not just bodily.  You mean bodily, emotional, and social consequences.

Don’t forget the intellectual consequences.

Like what?

If I make myself stupid, then I will end up even stupider than I had intended.  Works every time.

I’m not sure I understand you.

You should.  I’ve been talking about it for weeks.

Oh, I see – those stories you’ve been telling in your blog –

Yes?

Most of them are about the natural consequences of suppressing conscience.  Right?

Right.

So they’re about the natural consequences of making yourself stupid.

Yes.

But then they’re not about just one witness.

No.

They’re about two witnesses at once.  The first and the fourth.  Deep conscience and natural consequences.

Right again.

So the four witnesses don’t work independently.  They depend on each other.  They interact.  We need all four.

Exactly.  Do you notice how that takes us back to the question you asked at the beginning of the conversation?

That was last week.  What was it again?

You asked why what I call natural law doesn’t sound much like what thinkers like Hobbes and Locke called natural law.

Oh, right.

I said I work in the classical natural law tradition, but they were revisionists.  So you asked about the difference.

You’re going to tell me that thinkers like Thomas Hobbes and John Locke got natural law wrong because somehow or other they got the four witnesses wrong.  Correct?

Yes, but it’s even worse, because the revisionists didn’t even admit that there are four witnesses.  You see, they were simplifiers.

What do you mean?

The hallmark of classical natural law thinking is that it tries to weave all four witnesses into a tapestry.

So you’ve been saying.

But the revisionists tried to make their tapestries with fewer colors.  They always ignored or diminished at least one of the witnesses.

Illustrate.  Use Hobbes.

His theory recognized only one of the four witnesses.

Natural consequences?

Right on the first try.  Not only that, he recognized only one kind of natural consequence.

Violent death.

Right.  He considered man’s natural condition to be anarchy.  But in anarchy life was short.  According to him, we worked out moral laws in order to stay alive, and we invented government to enforce the moral laws.

But that’s not all wrong, is it?  Morality does help keep us from each other’s throats.

It does.

And government does enforce – never mind, I don’t want to say that.  Still, isn’t there something to be said for keeping one’s theory simple?  Occam’s Razor and all that.  Why clutter up the picture with unnecessary details?

Because they aren’t all unnecessary.

You’re saying the revisionists threw out some moral data.

Actually, a lot of it.

And I suppose throwing it out had natural consequences too?

Yes!  When you push some of the facts out the front door of your theory, you force them to try to creep in through the back door.  Worse yet –

Go on.

Worse yet, they may not succeed.

At what?

At creeping back in.

You’ve lost me again.

Would you mind not being found until next week?