Wagon Train

Wednesday, 02-10-2016

Question:

You’ve addressed prejudice in graduate admissions against serious Christians in two posts (by the way, your line “Cry reason and let slip the dogs of argument” is by far my new favorite quotation).  Fortunately, the people who wrote my own grad school recommendations were well aware of the problem.  But what, if anything, can be done to address the problem of hostile admissions committees?

P.S. I know you are a Renaissance man, but if you tell me you can speak Klingon, I will be truly amazed.  Please ease my curiosity on this matter.

Reply:

In the short run, almost nothing can be done; you can’t expect admissions committees to be reasonable when the universities themselves are unreasonable.  But if you take the long view, a lot can be done.  The real task is to build a new intellectual culture.

Undergrads should prepare not just by doing their coursework but by reading widely outside of it.  Excellent suggestions about what to read can be found in the Student Guides to the Major  Disciplines, available through the Intercollegiate Studies Institute.  Though you can purchase them, I believe PDF versions are available for free.  Christian students should also read widely in the classics of faith.  It’s amazing how much is available online – works of the Patristic writers such as St. Augustine’s Confessions and City of God, works of Thomas Aquinas such as the Summa Theologiae and Summa Contra Gentiles, and all sorts of other things like G.K. Chesterton’s Orthodoxy and The Everlasting Man and C.S. Lewis’s Mere Christianity, The Abolition of Man, and The Screwtape Letters.

Then get your foot in the door.  That’s why the second post warned grad school recommenders not to frighten the timid and easily-alarmed secularists on admissions committees by praising applicants for being persons of faith.

Once you get through the door, excel.  That’s what I meant in the first post when I wrote “Cry reason and let slip the dogs of argument.”  To be viewed as half as good, grad students who reject the secularist and relativist consensus will have to be twice as good – and I mean twice as good at using their minds.  Which is not a bad training.

Both during your graduate training and after you get your degree, think big.  The problem is that our intellectual culture is grounded on practical atheism; you don’t have to be an atheist, but you are expected to impersonate one.  Your calling is to work out the alternative.

Because you can’t even begin to work it out alone, join with other people are trying to do the same thing.  I’ve written about that lately too, here and here.  Think through the implications of Christian faith for scholarship.  Form intellectual wagon trains.  Be pioneers.

The very fact that you reject the prevailing academic ideology will offend many people.  Don’t shrink from tough critique, but distinguish between avoidable and unavoidable offense.  Be winsome.   Persuade.

Now as to your postscript.  I am sorry to disappoint you, but I am not a Renaissance man, and I don’t know a word of Klingon.  But I can tell you this:  vIq Hol Qatlh. mughmeH Qatlh. *

*Translation available.

 

 

A Richer Blend of Mondays

Tuesday, 02-09-2016

The most popular day on this blog is Monday, when I reply to letters I’ve received.  What do you think?  Should I run letters posts more often?

I wouldn’t fill the week with Mondays, but a richer blend of Mondays might be interesting.  Let’s try it.  If you are so inclined, write.  We’ll see how it goes.

 

The Consequences of Consequentialism

Monday, 02-08-2016

As my regular readers know, I reserve Mondays for letters.  This one is from an undergrad student.

Question:

The other day someone told me a scenario from the war in Bosnia in the 1990s.  As a matter of military policy, Serbian units systematically raped Bosnian women.  One soldier refused to participate.  As a punishment, his commander took the inhabitants of an internment camp, divided them in two, and ordered the soldier to kill half.  If the soldier refused, the officer would kill them all, and kill him too.

As St. Paul said, it is wrong to do evil so that good will result.  So I said the soldier should refuse to rape or murder no matter what the consequences.  The other guy was not convinced.  He thought the soldier should have given in because the results would have been better:  In the end, fewer people would have died.  How would you have answered him?

Reply:

The other guy's view is called “consequentialism.”  Consequentialism means that when you're deciding what to do, nothing matters but results.  Be sure you get the point:  Consequentialists don't just say results matter; we all believe that.  They argue that nothing else matters but results -- that results can turn intrinsic evil into good.  Is it all right to lie and cheat?  Is it all right to have an abortion?  Is it all right to sleep with your girlfriend?  Is it all right to commit atrocities?  The consequentialist’s answer will always be the same:  “It depends.”  What does it depend on? The results.

Can results really make intrinsic wrong right?  The question comes up every day, and it isn't just for armchair philosophers.  Consequentialism wrecks lives.  Also civilizations.  It has gone a long way toward wrecking ours.

It's difficult to get through to someone who takes the results-only line, but keep trying.  One way is to make your friend begin doubting his assumptions about what the results will be.  Another is to show him that ironically, the attitude “nothing matters but results” has bad results.  Best of all and most fundamental is get his conscience on your side -- to show him that something does matter besides results.

In your shoes, I might make one of the following points.  Don’t drop them all on your friend.  A conversation isn’t a bombing run.

1.  “Considering that genocide was Serbian policy, it would have been naïve to think that a promise like 'If you murder these, then I won't murder those' can be taken seriously.  The only real question facing the soldier was whether he would join in the murdering.”

2.  “The Serbians committed genocide for the sake of consequences that they considered better.  If the soldier agreed to participate in their murders for the sake of consequences that he considered better, then how would his hands be less dirty than theirs?”

3.  “Participating in murder for fear of consequences has a consequence too.  The consequence is that you yourself become a murderer.  Can you live with that?”

4.  “Sometimes those who commit atrocities are even more intent in getting others to cooperate with their atrocities.  So if you do become complicit, you’re not just helping them kill.  Aren’t you also helping them turn people like you into people like them?  And don’t you then acquire a motive not to bring them to justice, because you too would be punished?”

5.  “According to consequentialism, nothing whatsoever is intrinsically wrong -- not even systematic rape and genocide.  Anything whatsoever is okay if the consequences are good enough.  Look me in the eye.  Is that what you really believe?”

6.  “Suppose we all did become consequentialists.  We would then live in a world in which people did believe that nothing whatsoever is intrinsically wrong, in which they did believe that anything whatsoever is okay if it gets the results that we want.  What would be the results – the consequences -- if everyone did take that line?”

7.  “Is there anything you wouldn't do for the sake of results you liked better? Would you murder six million Jews, like Hitler?  Would you molest children?  Would you eat them?  Would you rape and torture your mother?  What -- did I hear you say “No”?  Did I hear you say that there is at least one thing you wouldn't do no matter what?  Then you admit consequentialism is wrong.”

Start with the last point. Most people are consequentialists only when their consciences don't hurt enough yet.

 

How the Meaning of Liberty Did and Didn’t Change

Sunday, 02-07-2016

Aristotle famously remarks that everything which the law does not expressly permit is forbidden.  Some people take this as showing how different the classical concept of liberty is from the modern one.  For we say just the opposite:  That everything which the law does not expressly forbid is permitted.

There really is a difference between the classical and modern concepts of liberty, but that isn’t it.  If Aristotle’s remark had been intended literally, it would be absurd.  Because of the law’s silence about rotation, respiration, and osculation, you would be forbidden to turn over in bed, take a breath, or kiss your spouse.

What Aristotle did mean by his comment isn’t clear, but there are all sorts of ways to make sense of it without taking it literally.  What he actually says is that “the law does not expressly permit suicide, and what it does not expressly permit it forbids.”  But suicide is self-murder, and murder is expressly forbidden by the law.  So some think he might mean only that in the context of an existing prohibition, any act for which the law does not expressly declare an exception is prohibited.

So if that isn’t it, then what is the difference between the classical and modern concepts of liberty?  Among the classical thinkers (bearing in mind that not all ancient thinkers were classical), the term “liberty” referred not to the absence of governance, but to a certain kind of governance -- whether over a multitude of people, a single man, or an aspect of a man.

Thus, in the political sense, the people of a republic were called “free” because they collectively ruled themselves (rather than being under the thumb of a tyrant).

In the domestic sense, a freeman was called “free” because he ruled himself (rather than being ruled by a master).

In the moral sense, a virtuous man was called “free” because he was ruled by the principle which most fully expressed his nature, his reason (rather than being at the mercy of his desires).

And in the religious sense, a Christian was called “free” because he served the Author of his being, in whose image he was made, apart from whom he could not truly be himself, for to be alienated from the one in whose image I am made is to be alienated from my own being.

By degrees, the meaning of the term changed.  So long as they do not think too deeply about the matter, modern people tend to regard freedom not as freedom from the wrong kind of rule, but as freedom from rule.

In the political sense, this would make the people of a republic freer than the people of a tyranny only if they happened to make fewer rules for themselves than a tyrant would.  In fact, the only true freedom would be anarchy, which has no rules at all, although freedom in this sense turns out to be inconvenient.

In the domestic sense, a freeman would be freer than a slave not because he ruled himself, but only because he was more nearly able to do as he pleased – if, in fact, he was more nearly able.  In the moral sense, a virtuous man would be freer than a vicious one only if his reason happened to put less constraint on his will than his base desires did.  The only true freedom would be following whatever impulse one happened to have at the moment.  However one might dress this up by calling it “autonomy,” as though we were gods, the condition is less superhuman than subhuman.

In the religious sense, a person would be free only if he served nothing and no one.  Since in this view of things, God looks like a tyrant, some suppose that the only free spirit is the atheist.  Carrying the modern line of reasoning still further, some take the view that not even the atheist is truly free, if he serves the cause of atheism.

The culmination of the modern idea is that no one is truly free unless he does what he does merely because he does it; unless he has no particular reason for doing anything at all; unless his choices are meaningless.  In this sense, freedom is not so much inconvenient as futile, and human existence is absurd.  Which is just what such people conclude.

 

Forms Are Conserved

Saturday, 02-06-2016

Nature exhibits organisms with one-chambered hearts, two-chambered hearts, three-chambered hearts, and four-chambered hearts.

A certain kind of thinker regards this as proof of Darwinism.  See?  First came the one-chambered heart, then the two, then the three, then the four.

But try to imagine a transition.  How could a species make a gradual transition from, say, a two- to a three-chambered heart?  No halfway house could function.

This is not an argument against descent with modification.  But it does count as a strong objection to the gradualist, adaptationist explanation of how the modifications happened.  Other things may evolve; basic forms are conserved.

I first came across the argument years ago in biochemist Michael Denton’s Evolution: A Theory in CrisisIt was the first work I had read which showed me that there might be purely scientific grounds to reject a theory which up to then I had considered unassailable.

What spurs the recollection is that Denton has just published a new book, Evolution:  Still a Theory in CrisisI look forward to reading it.

 

A Little Conversation about Value

Friday, 02-05-2016

“Nothing is objectively good for human beings; or at any rate, if anything is, there is no way to know.”

“Is that so?  Then put your finger in this candle flame.”

“I’ll do no such thing!”

“Why not?”

“Because it would hurt, as you well know.”

“So?”

“So I don't like pain, all right?”

“Why don’t you?”

“I see what you’re trying to do.  You want me to admit that pain is bad.  Have it your way: Pain is bad.  According to taste.”

“What do you mean, ‘According to taste?”

“I mean that it’s merely my subjective preference.  I make no claim that it holds in any objective sense.”

“You mean that it’s like your preference in flavors of ice cream?”

“Exactly.”

“What flavor do you like, by the way?”

“Chocolate.  Why?”

“Do you like vanilla?”

“Hate it.  You still haven’t told me why you’re asking.”

“Give me a moment.  Have you always liked chocolate?”

“No.  When I was a little boy I hated it.  I liked vanilla.”

“Doesn’t it distress you that you changed your mind?”

“Why should it?”

“Then it doesn’t?”

“No.”

“Why not?”

“Because it’s just a subjective preference, as I told you.  It makes no difference.”

“Do you find it upsetting to imagine yourself enjoying vanilla again in the future?”

“Of course not.”

“For the same reason, I suppose.”

“Yes, for the same reason.”

“Put your finger in this candle flame.”

“What’s the matter with you?  I told you, I don't want to get hurt.”

“I thought you might have changed your mind.”

“Why should I change my mind about a thing like that?”

“Just thought you might.”

“Well, I’m not about to.”

“But it doesn’t bother you to think that you might.”

“What?”

“I mean that you wouldn’t have any problem about becoming a masochist and seeking out painful experiences.”

“Are you trying to insult me?”

“Not at all.  Do you mean you don’t fancy becoming a masochist?”

“Of course I don’t.”

“But how is this subjective preference different from the other?”

“What do you mean, ‘different’?”

“Well, it doesn’t matter to you whether you prefer chocolate to vanilla, or vanilla to chocolate, so long as you get what you want at the moment.”

“True.  So?”

“Yet it does matter to you whether you prefer pleasure to pain, or pain to pleasure.  See the difference?”

“Yes, I see it now.”

“Good.  Now when you were explaining your tastes in ice cream, I understood you to mean that the reason it doesn’t matter to you whether you prefer chocolate to vanilla, or vanilla to chocolate, is that your preference for one over the other is, in your own view, purely subjective.”

“Drat.  I see where this is leading again.”

“Tell me.”

“You want me to say that if, whenever I regard my ordinary preference as purely subjective, I have no higher-order preference about what preference to have, then, whenever I do have a higher-order preference about what preference to have, I must regard my ordinary preference as other than purely subjective.”

“Right.  Go on.”

“And so in the ease of pleasure and pain, where I really do prefer to go on preferring pleasure, it must be my view deep down that my preference for pleasure over pain is objectively reasonable.”

“Well?”

***    *    ***

Do not reproach me for the brevity of this slice of conversation.   I know full well that no self-respecting philosopher would give in so quickly; that is not the point.  I am only offering an illustration, and you need not agree to any of the claims to which the speakers agreed.  All I ask you to recognize is that this conversation belongs to the genus of rational argument.

Seeing that, if you don’t like the way it was conducted, you may write a better one yourself -- or have a real one.

 

Pretenders

Thursday, 02-04-2016

When I was a grad student and a nihilist, I perceived that my closest professors also held nihilist assumptions, but they didn’t draw nihilist conclusions.  Of course this is still going on.

They too believed that judgments of good and evil have no rational foundation, but went about their daily life as though this made no difference.  They married, raised families, gossiped and argued as though these things actually made sense.

In a certain sense, so did I.  I took care of my children; I didn’t take up with other men’s wives.  But it bothered me that on my assumptions the central concerns of my life were mere preferences -- and it didn’t seem to bother them that on their assumptions the same thing was true of all of theirs.

My supervising professor found my attitude amusing.  Existential anxiety is so old fashioned.  Why all the anguish?  We’re not nihilists, we’re liberals.  Since judgments of good and evil have no rational foundation, why, then, we’ll all just get along.

This was expressed with many references to non-judgmentalism, moral neutrality, purely procedural democracy, John Rawls, and the virtue of doubting everything, which my supervisor called negative capacity.

But if judgments of good and evil have no rational foundation, I wondered, then why is getting along any better than cutting each other’s throats, and why is being doubtful about it better than being certain?  I saw my professors as smart but weak-nerved thinkers who couldn’t face the implications of their nihilism.  I resolved that my nerves would be stronger.

In aftertime (no longer a nihilist), I came to think I was mistaken.  There are no nihilists; there are only pretended nihilists.

The soft sort of nihilist certainly draws some of the conclusions of his premises:  Duties can’t be shirked, but preferences are infinitely fluid.  So if there are no duties, but only preferences, nihilism gives him a pre-arranged excuse for – why, anything he might need one for.  Of course the only reason one needs to prepare excuses is that one does know one’s duties.  So he isn’t really a nihilist after all.

But I was pretending too.  I thought I could accept my duties; what I couldn’t accept was that I had not made them myself.  I would rather have had Nothing than submit.  But then – even if not for the reason my supervisor gave – his mockery was right.  For why all the anguish?

After all, I had got what I wanted.